Showing posts with label science. Show all posts
Showing posts with label science. Show all posts

Saturday, 31 March 2018

A Pious Deception of Self-Creation

What follows is at times philosophical, at others poetic, and at others still, metaphorical. Yet at all times it is thoughtful. Overall, its subject is our world, our place in the world, our rhetorical context as living beings cast into a universe beyond us. If you hate thinking and do not see why human beings should contemplate then it is not for you. Leave, you will only annoy yourself. But if you can think and, even, dare to try to understand then you will find this of use. It requires no special knowledge or understanding outside from a few references the well read may recognise. But, in any case, those with the curiosity to seek further always will. And those without it won’t. That is their joy and the bounty that nature has bestowed upon them. But, for now, I relay to you a kind of myth and ask only that try to understand it….





How we, too, are still pious. - In science convictions have no rights of citizenship, as one says with good reason. Only when they decide to descend to the modesty of hypotheses, of a provisional experimental point of view, of a regulative fiction, they may be granted admission and even a certain value in the realm of knowledge - though always with the restriction that they remain under police supervision, under the police of mistrust. - But does this not mean, if you consider it more precisely, that a conviction may obtain admission to science only when it ceases to be a conviction? Would it not be the first step in the discipline of the scientific spirit that one would not permit oneself any more convictions?


Probably this is so; only we still have to ask: To make it possible for this discipline to begin, must there not be some prior conviction - even one that is so commanding arid unconditional that it sacrifices all other convictions to itself? We see that science also rests on a faith; there simply is no science "without presuppositions." The question whether truth is needed must not only have been affirmed in advance, but affirmed to such a degree that the principle, the faith, the conviction finds expression: “Nothing is needed more than truth, and in relation to it everything else has only second-rate value."


This unconditional will to truth - what is it? Is it the will not to allow oneself to be deceived? Or is it the will not to deceive? For the will to truth could be interpreted in the second way, too - if only the special case "I do not want to deceive myself" is subsumed under the generalization "I do not want to deceive." But why not deceive? But why not allow oneself to be deceived?


Note that the reasons for the former principle belong to an altogether different realm from those for the second. One does not want to allow oneself to be deceived because one assumes that it is harmful, dangerous, calamitous to be deceived. In this sense, science would be a long-range prudence, a caution, a utility; but one could object in all fairness: How is that? Is wanting not to allow oneself to be deceived really less harmful, less dangerous, less calamitous? What do you know in advance of the character of existence to be able to decide whether the greater advantage is on the side of the unconditionally mistrustful or of the unconditionally trusting? But if both should be required, much trust as well as much mistrust, from where would science then be permitted to take its unconditional faith or conviction on which it rests, that truth is more important than any other thing, including every other conviction? Precisely this conviction could never have come into being if both truth and untruth constantly proved to be useful, which is the case. Thus - the faith in science, which after all exists undeniably, cannot owe its origin to such a calculus of utility; it must have originated in spite of the fact that the disutility and dangerousness of “the will to truth," of “truth at any price” is proved to it constantly. "At any price'': how well we understand these words once we have offered and slaughtered one faith after another on this altar!


Consequently, "will to truth" does not mean "I will not allow myself to be deceived" but - there is no alternative - "I will not deceive, not even myself”; and with that we stand on moral ground. For you only have to ask yourself carefully, “Why do you not want to deceive?" especially if it should seem - and it does seem! - as if life aimed at semblance, meaning error, deception, simulation, delusion, self-delusion, and when the great sweep of life has actually always shown itself to be on the side of the most unscrupulous polytropoi. (“Polytropos” was a word used by Homer of Odysseus in the opening lines of The Odyssey. It describes his wily ability to deceive which, in the story, is what gets him safely home and vanquishes even his divine enemies.) Charitably interpreted, such a resolve might perhaps be a quixotism, a minor slightly mad enthusiasm; but it might also be something more serious, namely, a principle that is hostile to life and destructive. - “Will to truth" - that might be a concealed will to death.


Thus the question "Why science?" leads back to the moral problem: Why have morality at all when life, nature, and history are "not moral"? No doubt, those who are truthful in that audacious and ultimate sense that is presupposed by the faith in science thus affirm another world than the world of life, nature, and history; and insofar as they affirm this "other world" - look, must they not by the same token negate its counterpart, this world, our world? - But you will have gathered what I am driving at, namely, that it is still a metaphysical faith upon which our faith in science rests - that even we seekers after knowledge today, we godless anti-metaphysicians still take our fire, too, from the flame lit by a faith that is thousands of years old, that Christian faith which was also the faith of Plato, that God is the truth, that truth is divine. - But what if this should become more and more incredible, if nothing should prove to be divine anymore unless it were error, blindness, the lie - if God himself should prove to be our most enduring lie?


As interpreters of our experiences. - One sort of honesty has been alien to all founders of religions and their kind: They have never made their experiences a matter of conscience for knowledge. "What did I really experience? What happened in me and around me at that time? Was my reason bright enough? Was my will opposed to all deceptions of the senses and bold in resisting the fantastic?" None of them has asked such questions, nor do any of our dear religious people ask them even now. On the contrary, they thirst after things that go against reason, and they do not wish to make it too hard for themselves to satisfy it. So they experience "miracles” and "rebirths" and hear the voices of little angels! But we, we others who thirst after reason, are determined to scrutinize our experiences as severely as a scientific experiment - hour after hour, day after day. We ourselves wish to be our experiments and guinea pigs.


New struggles. - After Buddha was dead, his shadow was still shown for centuries in a cave - a tremendous, gruesome shadow. God is dead; but given the way of men, there may still be caves for thousands of years in which his shadow will be shown. - And we - we still have to vanquish his shadow, too. (Let us here not be dumb enough to imagine that what is meant is merely one sort of god.)


Let us beware.- Let us beware of thinking that the world is a living being. Where should it expand? On what should it feed? How could it grow and multiply? We have some notion of the nature of the organic; and we should not reinterpret the exceedingly derivative, late, rare, accidental, that we perceive only on the crust of the earth and make of it something essential, universal, and eternal, which is what those people do who call the universe an organism. This nauseates me. Let us even beware of believing that the universe is a machine: it is certainly not constructed for one purpose, and calling it a "machine" does it far too much honour.


Let us beware of positing generally and everywhere anything as elegant as the cyclical movements of our neighbouring stars; even a glance into the Milky Way raises doubts whether there are not far coarser and more contradictory movements there, as well as stars with eternally linear paths, etc. The astral order in which we live is an exception; this order and the relative duration that depends on it have again made possible an exception of exceptions: the formation of the organic. The total character of the world, however, is in all eternity chaos - in the sense not of a lack of necessity but of a lack of order, arrangement, form, beauty, wisdom, and whatever other names there are for our aesthetic anthropomorphisms. Judged from the point of view of our reason, unsuccessful attempts are by all odds the rule, the exceptions are not the secret aim, and the whole musical box repeats eternally its tune which may never be called a melody - and ultimately even the phrase “unsuccessful attempt" is too anthropomorphic and reproachful. But how could we reproach or praise the universe? Let us beware of attributing to it heartlessness and unreason or their opposites: it is neither perfect nor beautiful, nor noble, nor does it wish to become any of these things; it does not by any means strive to imitate man. None of our aesthetic and moral judgments apply to it. Nor does it have any instinct for self-preservation or any other instinct; and it does not observe any laws either. Let us beware of saying that there are laws in nature. There are only necessities: there is nobody who commands, nobody who obeys, nobody who trespasses. Once you know that there are no purposes, you also know that there is no accident; for it is only beside a world of purposes that the word “accident” has meaning. Let us beware of saying that death is opposed to life. The living is merely a type of what is dead, and a very rare type.


Let us beware of thinking that the world eternally creates new things. There are no eternally enduring substances; matter is as much of an error as the God of the Eleatics. But when shall we ever be done with our caution and care? When will all these shadows of God cease to darken our minds? When will we complete our de-deification of nature? When may we begin to “naturalise" humanity in terms of a pure, newly discovered, newly redeemed nature?


Origin of the logical. - How did logic come into existence in the human being's head? Certainly out of illogic, whose realm originally must have been immense. Innumerable beings who made inferences in a way different from ours perished; for all that, their ways might have been truer. Those, for example, who did not know how to find often enough what is "equal" as regards both nourishment and hostile animals - those, in other words, who subsumed things too slowly and cautiously - were favored with a lesser probability of survival than those who guessed immediately upon encountering similar instances that they must be equal. The dominant tendency, however, to treat as equal what is merely similar - an illogical tendency, for nothing is really equal - is what first created any basis for logic.


In order that the concept of substance could originate - which is indispensable for logic although in the strictest sense nothing real corresponds to it - it was likewise necessary that for a long time one did not see nor perceive the changes in things. The beings that did not see so precisely had an advantage over those that saw everything "in flux." At bottom, every high degree of caution in making inferences and every skeptical tendency constitute a great danger for life. No living beings would have survived if the opposite tendency - to affirm rather than suspend judgment, to err and make up things rather than wait, to assent rather than negate, to pass judgment rather than be just - had not been bred to the point where it became extraordinarily strong.


The course of logical ideas and inferences in our brain today corresponds to a process and a struggle among impulses that are, taken singly, very illogical and unjust. We generally experience only the result of this struggle because this primeval mechanism now runs its course so quickly and is so well concealed.


Cause and effect. - "Explanation" is what we call it, but it is "description" that distinguishes us from older stages of knowledge and science. Our descriptions are better - we do not explain any more than our predecessors. We have uncovered a manifold one-after-another where the naive person and inquirer of older cultures saw only two separate things. "Cause” and "effect" is what one says; but we have merely perfected the image of becoming without reaching beyond the image or behind it. In every case the series of "causes” confronts us much more completely, and we infer: first, this and that has to precede in order that this or that may then follow - but this does not involve any comprehension. In every chemical process, for example, quality appears as a "miracle," as ever; also, every locomotion; nobody has "explained" a push. But how could we possibly explain anything? We operate only with things that do not exist: lines, planes, bodies, atoms, divisible time spans, divisible spaces. How should explanations be at all possible when we first turn everything into an image, our image!


It will do to consider science as an attempt to humanise things as faithfully as possible; as we describe things and their one-after-another, we learn how to describe ourselves more and more precisely. Cause and effect: such a duality probably never exists; in truth we are confronted by a continuum out of which we isolate a couple of pieces, just as we perceive motion only as isolated points and then infer it without ever actually seeing it. The suddenness with which many effects stand out misleads us; actually it is sudden only for us. In this moment of suddenness there is an infinite number of processes that elude us. An intellect that could see cause and effect as a continuum and a flux and not, as we do, in terms of an arbitrary division and dismemberment, would repudiate the concept of cause and effect and deny all conditionality.


How far the moral sphere extends. - As soon as we see a new image, we immediately construct it with the aid of all our previous experiences depending on the degree of our honesty and justice. All experiences are moral experiences, even in the realm of sense perception.


The four errors. - Human beings have been educated by their errors. First, they always saw themselves only incompletely; second, they endowed themselves with fictitious attributes; third, they placed themselves in a false order of rank in relation to animals and nature; fourth, they invented ever new tables of goods and always accepted them for a time as eternal and unconditional: as a result of this, now one and now another human impulse and state held first place and was ennobled because it was esteemed so highly. If we removed the effects of these four errors, we should also remove humanity, humaneness, and "human dignity."


Life no argument. - We have arranged for ourselves a world in which we can live-by positing bodies, lines, planes, causes and effects, motion and rest, form and content; without these articles of faith nobody now could endure life. But that does not prove them. Life is no argument. The conditions of life might include error.


In the horizon of the infinite. - We have left the land and have embarked. We have burned our bridges behind us - indeed, we have gone farther and destroyed the land behind us. Now, little ship, look out! Beside you is the ocean: to be sure, it does not always roar, and at times it lies spread out like silk and gold and reveries of graciousness. But hours will come when you will realise that it is infinite and that there is nothing more awesome than infinity. Oh, the poor bird that felt free and now strikes the walls of this cage! Woe, when you feel homesick for the land as if it had offered more freedom - and there is no longer any "land."


The madman.- Have you not heard of that madman who lit a lantern in the bright morning hours, ran to the marketplace. and cried incessantly: "I seek God! I seek God!'' - As many of those who did not believe in God were standing around just then, he provoked much laughter. Has he got lost? asked one. Did he lose his way like a child? asked another. Or is he hiding? Is he afraid of us? Has he gone on a voyage? emigrated? - Thus they yelled and laughed.

The madman jumped into their midst and pierced them with his eyes. “Whither is God?" he cried; "I will tell you. We have killed him - you and I. All of us are his murderers. But how did we do this? How could we drink up the sea? Who gave us the sponge to wipe away the entire horizon? What were we doing when we unchained this earth from its sun? Whither is it moving now? Whither are we moving? Away from all suns? Are we not plunging continually? Backward, sideward, forward, in all directions? Is there still any up or down? Are we not straying as through an infinite nothing? Do we not feel the breath of empty space? Has it not become colder? Is not night continually closing in on us? Do we not need to light lanterns in the morning? Do we hear nothing as yet of the noise of the gravediggers who are burying God? Do we smell nothing as yet of the divine decomposition? Gods, too, decompose. God is dead. God remains dead. And we have killed him.


"How shall we comfort ourselves, the murderers of all murderers? What was holiest and mightiest of all that the world has yet owned has bled to death under our knives: who will wipe this blood off us? What water is there for us to clean ourselves? What festivals of atonement, what sacred games shall we have to invent? Is not the greatness of this deed too great for us? Must we ourselves not become gods simply to appear worthy of it? There has never been a greater deed; and whoever is born after us - for the sake of this deed he will belong to a higher history than all history hitherto."


Here the madman fell silent and looked again at his listeners; and they, too, were silent and stared at him in astonishment. At last he threw his lantern on the ground, and it broke into pieces and went out. "I have come too early," he said then; "my time is not yet. This tremendous event is still on its way, still wandering; it has not yet reached the ears of men. Lightning and thunder require time; the light of the stars requires time; deeds, though done, still require time to be seen and heard. This deed is still more distant from them than the most distant stars - and yet they have done it themselves.”


It has been related further that on the same day the madman forced his way into several churches and there struck up his requiem aeternam deo. Led out and called to account, he is said always to have replied nothing but: "What after all are these churches now if they are not the tombs and sepulchers of God?”


Mystical explanations.- Mystical explanations are considered deep. The truth is that they are not even superficial.


Long live physics! - How many people know how to observe something? Of the few who do, how many observe themselves? "Everybody is farthest away - from themselves"; all who try the reins know this to their chagrin, and the maxim "know thyself!" addressed to human beings by a god, is almost malicious. That the case of self-observation is indeed as desperate as that is attested best of all by the manner in which almost everybody talks about the essence of moral actions - this quick, eager, convinced, and garrulous manner with its expression, its smile, and its obliging ardour! One seems to have the wish to say to you: "But my dear friend, precisely this is my specialty. You have directed your question to the one person who is entitled to answer you. As it happens, there is nothing about which I am as wise as about this. To come to the point: when a human being judges 'this is right' and then infers 'therefore it must be done: and then proceeds to do what he has thus recognized as right and designated as necessary - then the essence of his action is moral."


But my friend, you are speaking of three actions instead of one. When you judge "this is right," that is an action, too. Might it not be possible that one could judge in a moral and in an immoral manner? Why do you consider this, precisely this, right?


"Because-this is what my conscience tells me; and the voice of conscience is never immoral, for it alone determines what is to be moral."


But why do you listen to the voice of your conscience? And what gives you the right to consider such a judgment true and infallible? For this faith - is there no conscience for that? Have you never heard of an intellectual conscience? A conscience behind your “conscience"? Your judgment "this is right" has a pre-history in your instincts, likes, dislikes, experiences, and lack of experiences. "How did it originate there?” you must ask, and then also: "What is it that impels me to listen to it?" You can listen to its commands like a good soldier who hears his officer's command. Or like a woman who loves the man who commands. Or like a flatterer and coward who is afraid of the commander. Or like a dunderhead who obeys because no objection occurs to him. In short, there are a hundred ways in which you can listen to your conscience. But that you take this or that judgment for the voice of conscience - in other words, that you feel something to be right - may be due to the fact that you have never thought much about yourself and simply have accepted blindly that what you had been told ever since your childhood was right; or it may be due to the fact that what you call your duty has up to this point brought you sustenance and honours - and you consider it "right" because it appears to you as your own "condition of existence" (and that you have a right to existence seems irrefutable to you).


For all that, the firmness of your moral judgment could be evidence of your personal abjectness, of impersonality; your "moral strength" might have its source in your stubbornness - or in your inability to envisage new ideals. And, briefly, if you had thought more subtly, observed better, and learned more, you certainly would not go on calling this "duty" of yours and this “conscience" of yours duty and conscience. Your understanding of the manner in which moral judgments have originated would spoil these grand words for you, just as other grand words, like "sin" and "salvation of the soul" and "redemption" have been spoiled for you. - And now don't cite the categorical imperative, my friend! This term tickles my ear and makes me laugh despite your serious presence. It makes me think of the old Kant who had obtained the "thing in itself” by stealth - another very ridiculous thing !- and was punished for this when the "categorical imperative” crept stealthily into his heart and led him astray - back to "God," "soul," "freedom,” and "immortality," like a fox who loses his way and goes astray back into his cage. Yet it had been his strength and cleverness that had broken open the cage!


What? You admire the categorical imperative within you? This "firmness" of your so-called moral judgment? This "unconditional'' feeling that "here everyone must judge as I do"? Rather admire your selfishness at this point. And the blindness, pettiness, and frugality of your selfishness. For it is selfish to experience one's own judgment as a universal law; and this selfishness is blind, petty, and frugal because it betrays that you have not yet discovered yourself nor created for yourself an ideal of your own, your very own - for that could never be somebody else’s and much less that of all, all!


Anyone who still judges "in this case everybody would have to act like this'' has not yet taken five steps toward self-knowledge. Otherwise they would know that there neither are nor can be actions that are the same: that every action that has ever been done was done in an altogether unique and irretrievable way, and that this will be equally true of every future action; that all regulations about actions relate only to their coarse exterior (even the most inward and subtle regulations of all moralities so far); that these regulations may lead to some semblance of sameness, but really only to some semblance; that as one contemplates or looks back upon any action at all, it is and remains impenetrable; that our opinions about "good” and "noble” and "great" can never be proved true by our actions because every action is unknowable; that our opinions, valuations, and tables of what is good certainly belong among the most powerful levers in the involved mechanism of our actions, but that in any particular case the law of their mechanism is indemonstrable.


Let us therefore limit ourselves to the purification of our opinions and valuations and to the creation of our own new tables of what is good, and let us stop brooding about the "moral value of our actions”! Yes, my friends, regarding all the moral chatter of some about others it is time to feel nauseous. Sitting in moral judgment should offend our taste. Let us leave such chatter and such bad taste to those who have nothing else to do but drag the past a few steps further through time and who never live in the present - which is to say the many, the great majority. We, however, want to become those we are - human beings who are new, unique, incomparable, who give themselves laws, who create themselves. To that end we must become the best learners and discoverers of everything that is lawful and necessary in the world: we must become physicists in order to be able to be creators in this sense - while hitherto all valuations and ideals have been based on ignorance of physics or were constructed so as to contradict it. Therefore: long live physics! And even more so that which compels us to turn to physics - our honesty!


The meaning of our cheerfulness. - The greatest recent event - that “God is dead,” that the belief in the Christian god has become unbelievable - is already beginning to cast its first shadows over Europe. For the few at least, whose eyes - the suspicion in whose eyes is strong and subtle enough for this spectacle, some sun seems to have set and some ancient and profound trust has been turned into doubt; to them our old world must appear daily more like evening, more mistrustful, stranger, “older.” But in the main one may say: The event itself is far too great, too distant, too remote from the multitude's capacity for comprehension even for the tidings of it to be thought of as having arrived as yet. Much less may one suppose that many people know as yet what this event really means - and how much must collapse now that this faith has been undermined because it was built upon this faith, propped up by it, grown into it; for example, the whole of our European morality. This long plenitude and sequence of breakdown, destruction, ruin, and cataclysm that is now impending - who could guess enough of it today to be compelled to play the teacher and advance proclaimer of this monstrous logic of terror, the prophet of a gloom and an eclipse of the sun whose like has probably never yet occurred on earth?


Even we born guessers of riddles who are, as it were, waiting on the mountains, posted between today and tomorrow, stretched in the contradiction between today and tomorrow, we firstlings and premature births of the coming century, to whom the shadows that must soon envelop Europe really should have appeared by now - why is it that even we look forward to the approaching gloom without any real sense of involvement and above all without any worry and fear for ourselves? Are we perhaps still too much under the impression of the initial consequences of this event - and these initial consequences, the consequences for ourselves, are quite the opposite of what one might perhaps expect: They are not at all sad and gloomy but rather like a new and scarcely describable kind of light, happiness, relief, exhilaration, encouragement, dawn.


Indeed, we philosophers and "free spirits” feel, when we hear the news that "the old god is dead," as if a new dawn shone on us; our heart overflows with gratitude, amazement, premonitions, expectation. At long last the horizon appears free to us again, even if it should not be bright; at long last our ships may venture out again, venture out to face any danger; all the daring of the lover of knowledge is permitted again; the sea, our sea, lies open again; perhaps there has never yet been such an ''open sea”.


Taken from sections 344, 319, 108, 109, 111, 112, 114, 115, 121, 124, 125, 126, 335 and 343 of Die Fröhliche Wissenschaft by Friedrich Nietzsche.

Tuesday, 29 December 2015

Science, Consciousness, Argument and Materialism

Are you conscious? Do you have a consciousness? You instinctively want to answer "Yes" and maybe you think its rather dumb of me to even ask the question, so common-sensical does the answer "Yes" seem to you. But a number of scientists and philosophers, extremely materialist ones, would say that you aren't. And neither are they. They think your sense of consciousness is a very powerful illusion and that it is a function of your brain to generate this illusion. Of course, they think this partly, maybe even mostly, because they have a dogmatic view of reality as a whole. They think that everything is explainable in physical terms, in terms of physics and chemistry. So you can't really have a consciousness because that does not admit of a physical explanation. Therefore, they say, your sense of consciousness must be something the brain is doing. These people do not so much explain consciousness as explain it away.

It was with some enthusiasm that in a post-Christmas lull of activity I dived into texts and online video about varying views on human consciousness. Forty eight hours later that enthusiasm had been severely tempered if not completely extinguished. I had been following my thoughts where they led me, from this text to that, from one video to similar suggested ones. New thoughts and thinkers came up on my radar. I learnt that consciousness is very much a shibboleth for many, a stumbling block. Very soon I was into debates and forums and that is when things started to get too much. My head started to bulge and ache. Too much information, too much arguing, too much partisanship. I reflected on this. Why is so much modern debate cheap, adversarial and sarcastic with an undertone of nastiness on the side? Why are people so self-invested in their intellectual choices? Why is every thought laid down as a personal Waterloo?  

I'm mixing my discussions here in this blog. On the one hand, I'm wanting to research and discuss varying human views on consciousness but, on the other, I find myself discouraged by how my own species, human beings, seem to behave and go about that. In any debate these days, most carried out in the febrile melting pot / echo chamber / outrage arena that is the Internet, it will take very few steps indeed to go from discussing a subject to insulting the person raising the subject of the discussion to insulting many of the other participants in it as well. The next stage is getting your army of followers to descend from Valhalla and unleash hell on those holding views you cannot believe yourself. Battle lines are quickly drawn and thereafter all anyone does is defend the position they are entrenched in. More heat than light results and anyone who was there to try and learn from others and their points of view is quickly and thoroughly made cynical. Debate today, I conclude, is often conducted in the gutter and the aim of it is to score points, get hits on your opponent and employ as much ridicule as possible. Its UFC over points of view and beliefs. Am I naive for wanting to share and learn and thinking this might even be possible? Am I naive to want merely a lucid detachment, a humble enquiry?

I came across the work of a scientist called Rupert Sheldrake. He started out very mainstream and was educated in orthodoxy at the heart of all things thought right and good about science. As a biologist, he got a PhD from Cambridge, UK, had fellowships at the Royal Society and at Harvard and even made discoveries which were lauded in all the right journals, including Nature. But then he published a book in which he discussed "morphic fields" and spoke about "resonance" and "formative causation". As far as I can tell, Sheldrake was started down this path by asking himself why plants take the form they have. We might think this is to do with genes and DNA (in other words, a materialist answer) but this turns out not to be the case and this information supplies only a fraction of what is needed. (Sheldrake describes the Human Genome Project as a bit of a failure because the secrets people hoped to unlock by it have not come to pass.) We don't know how plants know to grow and look a certain way or why they look the same as the others like them. 

Sheldrake proposed what I understand as some kind of memory field. Basically, plants know how to grow because they know how other plants like them grew in the past. This holds true for animals too. For example, teach an animal to do something somewhere in the world and then other animals like it will learn the same thing much faster next time because they now somehow have the knowledge the other animal like them gained. The blurb for Sheldrake's book says

"the past forms and behaviors of organisms..... influence organisms in the present through direct connections across time and space".

Yes, I know it sounds a bit incredible but then if I'd told you the Earth went around the sun at some point in time you would have thought that silly too. (Also please note I'm not saying that this theory convinces me. To be honest, I haven't read the literature on it thoroughly enough to come to any conclusion at this point. I can say I have described it with far too little explanation here and maybe not too well so go read Sheldrake's books for a fuller and more adequate description of it. His experimental results that I read about, however, did make me think and sit up and take some notice.)

The book Sheldrake published, A New Science of Life, was denounced as heresy (yes, literally) against a materialist view of the world, the standard scientific view of the world that is put forward today and, thereafter, Sheldrake was viewed by the defenders of the mainstream and of this view of the world with a snigger and a sneer. The editor of Nature asked in an open review of the book if it should not, in fact, be burned. This is unfortunate because Sheldrake appears himself to be quite a reserved, quietly spoken and profoundly scientific man. Its important to note here that this is the case whether you happen to think there is something in his scientific hypotheses or not. To my mind Sheldrake is merely a very curious and scientific man who happens to want to investigate things other people don't. This is something to be praised, is it not? If you follow where evidence leads you should not stop if you start saying things that might threaten your career, your standing or your status within a professional field. Evidence leads where it must. But for many it doesn't. Some things are ruled kooky, off limits and things you don't talk about in polite society by those more concerned with careers than ideas.

Sheldrake thereafter started to follow his nose regarding his ideas and developed theories about consciousness (which is why he comes into my blog today) and things such as telepathy, things which a materialist would look upon as magic and impossible. He devised and carried out a number of methodologically scientific trials to test for things such as telepathy. For example, he ran trials in dogs to see if they knew when people might be coming home and on the sense people have of being stared at. He also ran trials to do with people thinking of someone who then, seemingly by coincidence, phones them. He was involved with trials on rats, teaching them tricks and then observing if other rats elsewhere could learn the same tricks faster as a result. In all these areas Sheldrake was trying to establish, on the basis of the scientific method, if there was more to things like this than blind luck or random chance. He determined that there was and laid out his results in the standard scientific fashion. He debated the results with skeptics (even challenging them to replicate his experiments) who seemed to disagree more with his conclusions and his implicit criticisms of their materialist boundaries than his methods and even though they themselves had no possible other solution to the issues he was raising and the results he presented. There was no substantial refutation of his experiments, their methodology or results. More so there was simply a refusal to accept or discuss them as there is to this day.

Today Sheldrake has moved on to a meta-discussion about science itself, a thing he sees as being held in the grip of a destructive materialism. The issue is that for those of a materialist persuasion non-materialist answers to questions are declared impossible from the off. Sheldrake finds this self-defeating and not very scientific in itself. His latest book, known as Science Set Free in the USA and as The Science Delusion in the UK, is an attempt to name 10 current "dogmas" of the scientific worldview (which Sheldrake would say has largely coalesced with the materialist position)  which are holding it back. He diagnoses that science itself has largely become a creed to be defended rather than that spirit of disinterested curiosity that maybe it should be. There are many prominent defenders of this scientific faith who are, moreover, extremely militant atheists (people like Richard Dawkins, P Z Myers and Daniel Dennett, to name but three) who actively look to police science and the public debate about it to the detriment, so Sheldrake would submit, of scientific endeavour as a whole. For sake of completeness I'll list Sheldrake's 10 "dogmas" of materialistic science below which he describes as "the 10 core beliefs that most scientists take for granted." (I have put some text in bold to highlight the main points.)



1. Everything is essentially mechanical. Dogs, for example, are complex mechanisms, rather than living organisms with goals of their own. Even people are machines, “lumbering robots,” in Richard Dawkins' vivid phrase, with brains that are like genetically programmed computers.

2. All matter is unconscious. It has no inner life or subjectivity or point of view. Even human consciousness is an illusion produced by the material activities of brains.

3. The total amount of matter and energy is always the same (with the exception of the Big Bang, when all the matter and energy of the universe suddenly appeared).

4. The laws of nature are fixed. They are the same today as they were at the beginning, and they will stay the same forever.

5. Nature is purposeless, and evolution has no goal or direction.

6. All biological inheritance is material, carried in the genetic material, DNA, and in other material structures.

7. Minds are inside heads and are nothing but the activities of brains. When you look at a tree, the image of the tree you are seeing is not “out there,” where it seems to be, but inside your brain.

8. Memories are stored as material traces in brains and are wiped out at death.

9. Unexplained phenomena like telepathy are illusory

10. Mechanistic medicine is the only kind that really works.


We can see here that Sheldrake's concern is to emphasize how much the materialistic creed is one which rules out certain areas of study or explanation as a matter of dogmatic concern. He himself wishes to refute them all. So materialism is essentially a faith that dare not speak its name. As I have said on my blog before, those like Richard Dawkins who hold this view are not the opposite of a religious believer: they are a religious believer and their religion is materialism. For example, to take the final of Sheldrake's points, materialists, so Sheldrake submits, would rule out any kind of healing or medicine that was not on the basis of the body being thought of mechanistically. So drugs are fine (since they treat the body as a big chemistry set that needs all the chemicals in balance) but holistic, alternative or other therapies are regarded as New Age and hokey folk magic. 

Sheldrake would also argue that the so-called "placebo effect" (where someone gets an inert pill thinking its actual medicine but gets better anyway) or the power of prayer or simply willing yourself to get better are also problematic for those of a mechanistic, materialist persuasion because such a point of view rules such things off limits as possibilities and, by definition, can have no explanation for them. If people could think themselves or be thought better that would present an insurmountable challenge to the materialist worldview which demands physical causes for physical things. Sheldrake is saying "Why not investigate this?" whilst others laugh and snigger at the very idea. Which seems more scientific to you?



So what to think of all this? Immediately one must admit that to accept Sheldrake's criticism of a science held in the grip of materialist dogma is not to accept his own positive contributions or theories regarding alternatives or additions to it. These are separate things and one is not committed to both by accepting one. Interestingly, in many of the forums and blogs I read about Sheldrake's criticisms of science the most common refutation was that "real scientists don't really think the way Sheldrake says they do". Sheldrake was accused of building a handy straw man it was easy to hack down. But I'm not so sure this is true. I see plenty of evidence at hand that science and scientific worldviews are held in the grip of a mechanistic materialism, one falling apart in the modern physical world of processes, energy and waves. I also take Sheldrake's point that all too many prominent scientists today are virulent atheists against anything that could be regarded as spiritual, mysterious or unexplainable from within a mechanistic materialist paradigm. Sheldrake correctly asserts that this position is held as a dogma. How else to explain those like Richard Dawkins who speaks of "wonder" on the one hand but "blind watchmakers" on the other? The watch image gives Dawkins away: the universe is like clockwork. Sheldrake is correct: there are those out to expunge beliefs in immaterial things or explanations and to make them, in a way quite Orwellian, unthinkable thoughts.

I am against this not because I believe in ghosts and ghouls, in gods and monsters, but because it is to artificially close off areas of enquiry for no other reason than that you personally don't believe in them. This seems a very dumb and thoroughly unscientific thing to do for me. You may regard Sheldrake's own theories as foolish and that is OK. It would be scientific to demonstrate that though if science is your game. The trouble is the most regular response to Sheldrake's own experiments is to ignore them. Some skeptics, he reports, have replicated his experiments and largely replicated his results too. But they are shy of doing this. In one debate Sheldrake reports that Richard Dawkins, another biologist, flat refused to debate his evidence preferring to criticize Sheldrake's refusal to take up the materialist position instead. Often this is done from a supposed position of power as the utility of science is lauded and, indeed, this cannot be denied. But it is surely relevant that those who endlessly chirp on and on about their passion for truth (as Dawkins does ad infinitum) should be criticized for their dogmatic assertion that truth will only be found in one place and not in others. Sheldrake is right to say that enquiry should go where it leads in a spirit of disinterested curiosity. Dawkins and his like are notable only for their remarkable lack of such curiosity where some things are concerned. This is a dogma, a boundary of faith.

And this is the point where the partisanship of modern day debate kicks in. By now you've made your choice and chosen a side I wouldn't be surprised to find out. But is it really about taking sides? My blog here is presented as the rambling thoughts of a man going through life just trying to understand the things that go on around him and sometimes impinge upon his own life and existence. That is what it is. I hope to do this in a spirit of somewhat lucid detachment. I don't need to defend my thoughts or my position because they are mine. I'm not saying everyone or even anyone else has to believe them. Its simply about me having a very naive honesty as much as I can. I'm well aware that my experience is narrow and that I know very, very little about anything. That is why the fact that you can read and communicate with others is a very good thing because you can take what they share and add it to your own data for analysis. But that doesn't happen as much as it should because confessional boundaries come into play and defensive walls get built by those more interested in defending what they think they've got than exploring together in a spirit of mutual curiosity. This is a source of great frustration. We live in a very public world where it is easy to belittle others and many can't resist the temptation for an easy "win" as they see it, often based merely on a numbers game.

Often in my thinking I find something interesting to read and, underneath, there is now the seemingly mandatory "comments" section. Often this is just hell. People of dubious qualifications (although this doesn't matter and is really an ad hominem approach) launch straight into personal attacks on those who think one thing or another. It doesn't really matter what they believe. What's important is that someone else doesn't believe it and that makes those who do stupid beyond belief. I find the whole exercise stupid beyond belief and I wish there were more places where debate could be to the point and not to the person (which is by far the biggest problem in any kind of discussion, that the subject switches from what is believed to who it is that believes it). Many times in comments sections about Sheldrake's books or work there are just insults tossed casually Sheldrake's way because he is that crazy guy who thinks dogs know telepathically when their masters are coming home. In a world of public forums you get a reputation and that reputation usurps the place that should have been reserved for consideration of the arguments. People get lazy and where formerly they needed to think now they just take "the word on the street" under advisement. There is a nihilistic schadenfreude at play that loves to tear down rather than build up.

There seems, not for the first time in one of my blogs, a lack of humility in many, if not most, people who debate these things. Sheldrake diagnoses this problem too when he says the problem is that some people these days think that science has resolved all the issues and now all we need to do is fill out the details. He gives examples from the ends of both the 19th and 20th centuries of people who have written that science will from now on discover less and less because we have already found out about most things. Its a matter of time not possibility. If we go on long enough we will answer all our questions and understand everything there is to understand. This belief strikes me as both arrogant and egotistical (as well as philosophically naive that there would be one answer to any question in the first place). Why, as Thomas Nagel writes in another recent book criticizing the materialist dogma, Mind and Cosmos, should any of the questions about the universe be within our power to answer? Doesn't that seem just a little bit egotistical to you, that human beings automatically must have the ability to understand? Why would all the answers of the universe be, as it were, human-shaped in their resolution, much less human-shaped and materialist? Is this a post-experimental conclusion or a pre-reflective condition? For the materialistic dogmatists this can only be because they have willed it so, forming a clockwork universe that can be measured and reproduced. But what happens when, finally, they are forced to accept that the clockwork was merely their illusion, a function of their indefatigable will to believe, another phase in human history?

It was the American philosopher and psychologist William James who said "We have the right to believe at our own risk any hypothesis that is live enough to tempt our will" (italics mine). He said this in the context of explaining why he thought people had a right, if not a duty, to hold religious beliefs which they found themselves genuinely unable to escape the force of. He did it by expounding a general theory of human belief across the board and did not make any special exceptions for religious beliefs, something some would want to do today in these more polemical times. Of course, believing something does not make it a scientific belief nor one that attains the recommendation of that credit but this is another matter involving the tenets of scientific peer review and debate. Beliefs are things which, for most people most of the time, function as true, even where they are contradictory from one person to the next. It is, when you think about it, common-sensically true that this is the case and the world keeps on turning nevertheless. Indeed, our world of sense and sensibility is the one which allows this state of affairs. For some this will be irrationalism but is it really? I sense I may need further blogs on this and I hope to provide them but, for now, it is enough for me to say that one person's shibboleth is another's possibility. Where our world allows us to hold such a belief others should not be so dogmatic as to dismiss another's opportunity to explore it or so authoritarian as to disallow it. This is not to take sides in the debate or nail one's colors to the mast. There is a time and place for that. It is to say that for all genuine people holding their beliefs is not a choice but a necessity.

All this puts me in mind of something Nietzsche pointed to when he said that "Truth" was but the history of Man's "irrefutable errors". This thought puts in question if we ever really know anything in an absolute sense, the sense that a "law" of the universe would rightly have. I would argue that Nietzsche's insight tends to suggest that we may not. But the good news is that we may not need to in any case. We have happily got by on our habits of belief and our practical observations of the universe until now and there is no suggestion from anywhere that we will ever need anything else to do so. We don't need to make of the universe a mechanism nor say that everything that is must, as a dogma, be physical. Indeed, the vast majority of our species has got on with life just fine without ever concerning themselves with such specialized technicalities. We can be be sure that even the world's most dogmatic scientist would have to agree that we do not know everything, nor even how much there is to know and how much we know of it. But it doesn't matter. We get on fine anyway. I would humbly suggest that the best way forward is to let people explore where their beliefs take them in a spirit of disinterested curiosity and let us see where that takes us.